generated from nerf/texTemplate
tired and scared
This commit is contained in:
parent
ac0ce99bb5
commit
9124739cca
3 changed files with 1174 additions and 850 deletions
10
src/Main.tex
10
src/Main.tex
|
@ -129,6 +129,10 @@
|
|||
\newcommand*{\TFF}{\ensuremath{\mathrm{TF}}\xspace}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\CF}{\ensumermath{\mathrm{CF}}\xspace}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\Ct}{\ensuremath{\mathcal{C}_t}\xspace}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\U}{\ensuremath{\mathcal{U}_κ}\xspace}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\Ud}{\ensumermath{\dot{\mathcal{U}}_κ}\xspace}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\V}{\ensuremath{\mathcal{V}_κ}\xspace}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\Vd}{\ensuremath{\dot{\mathcal{V}}_κ}\xspace}
|
||||
|
||||
\newcommand*{\Hom}{\mathrm{Hom}}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\Ho}{\mathrm{Ho}}
|
||||
|
@ -148,9 +152,9 @@
|
|||
\renewcommand*{\d}{\mathsf{d}}
|
||||
\renewcommand*{\i}{\textsf{i}}
|
||||
\renewcommand*{\t}{\mathsf{t}}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\⊗}{\mathbin{\hat{⊗}}}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\×}{\mathbin{\hat{×}}}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\at}{\mathbin{\hat{@}}}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\⊗}{\mathbin{\widehat{⊗}}}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\×}{\mathbin{\widehat{×}}}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\at}{\mathbin{\widehat{@}}}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\□}{\ensuremath{\widehat{□}}\xspace}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\Δ}{\ensuremath{\widehat{Δ}}\xspace}
|
||||
\newcommand*{\dCube}{\ensuremath{□_{∧∨}}\xspace}
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -18,8 +18,8 @@ equivariant model structure is also know as the ACCRS model structure.
|
|||
% reference for uniform fibrations CCHM and
|
||||
The “usual” model structure on this cube category is not equivalent to spaces, as shown
|
||||
by Buchholtz. %TODO find citation
|
||||
If we build the qutoient by swapping the dimensions of a square, the resulting space is not
|
||||
contractable, while in spaces it is. The idea is to correct this defect, by making the embedding
|
||||
If we build the quotient by swapping the dimensions of a square, the resulting space is not
|
||||
contractible, while in spaces it is. The idea is to correct this defect, by making the embedding
|
||||
of the point a trivial cofibration. This is archived by forcing an extra property onto
|
||||
the fibrations.
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -30,8 +30,8 @@ the fibrations.
|
|||
\end{tikzcd}
|
||||
\end{equation*} % Fix twist of suboject
|
||||
|
||||
Here \(σ\) is the map that swaps the dimenisons and \(e\) is the coequilizer map. The hope would be, that
|
||||
the coequilizer, would now present a lift for the right most lifting problem. But in general that
|
||||
Here \(σ\) is the map that swaps the dimensions and \(e\) is the coequalizer map. The hope would be, that
|
||||
the coequalizer, would now present a lift for the right most lifting problem. But in general that
|
||||
does not hold, the lifts have neither to commute with \(σ\) nor with \(\id\). The path forward
|
||||
will be to restrict the fibrations to have the desired property.
|
||||
%
|
||||
|
@ -39,10 +39,10 @@ will be to restrict the fibrations to have the desired property.
|
|||
% \subsubsection{Weak factorization systems}
|
||||
% If we force additional properties on our lifting problems, one might rightfully
|
||||
% ask if these indeed induce a weak factorization system (wfs). It is also unclear if
|
||||
% there are induced factorizations at all. The good news is, there is a refined version
|
||||
% there are induced factorization at all. The good news is, there is a refined version
|
||||
% of the small object argument \cref{smallObject}, that will help us out. This works on
|
||||
% the back of algebraic weak factorization systems. We don't need the whole theory and
|
||||
% get by with the following definitiont.
|
||||
% get by with the following definition.
|
||||
%
|
||||
% \begin{definition}\label{def:rightMaps}
|
||||
% Let \J be category and \(J : \J → \M^→\) be a functor. Then an object \(f\) in
|
||||
|
@ -65,14 +65,14 @@ will be to restrict the fibrations to have the desired property.
|
|||
% \end{definition}
|
||||
%
|
||||
% \begin{remark}
|
||||
% If we start with a set \J and make it into a discret category, then we will get our old definition
|
||||
% If we start with a set \J and make it into a discrete category, then we will get our old definition
|
||||
% of right lifting map, with an additional choice function for lifts. Which exists anyway if we
|
||||
% are ready to believe in strong enough choice principles.
|
||||
% \end{remark}
|
||||
%
|
||||
% After we defined a class of right maps by those lifting problems, it is not clear that these
|
||||
% will yield a wfs.
|
||||
% To get those we invoke a refinment of Quillens small object argument, namely
|
||||
% To get those we invoke a refinement of Quillens small object argument, namely
|
||||
% Garners small object argument \cite{garnerUnderstandingSmallObject2009}. This has the additional benefit of producing
|
||||
% algebraic weak factorization systems (awfs). For a quick reference see
|
||||
% \cite{riehlMadetoOrderWeakFactorization2015a}, and for an extensive tour \cite{riehlAlgebraicModelStructures2011}, or
|
||||
|
@ -80,7 +80,7 @@ will be to restrict the fibrations to have the desired property.
|
|||
% us is the following theorem \cite[][Theorem 2.28]{riehlAlgebraicModelStructures2011}
|
||||
%
|
||||
% \begin{theorem}[Garner]\label{smallObject}
|
||||
% Let \(\M\) be a cocomplete category satisfying either of the following conditions.
|
||||
% Let \(\M\) be a co-complete category satisfying either of the following conditions.
|
||||
% \begin{itemize}
|
||||
% \item[(\(*\))] Every \(X ∈ \M\) is \(α_X\)-presentable for some regular cardinal \(α_X\).
|
||||
% \item[(\dagger)] Every \(X ∈ \M\) is \(α_X\)-bounded with respect to some proper, well-copowered
|
||||
|
@ -89,8 +89,8 @@ will be to restrict the fibrations to have the desired property.
|
|||
% Let \( J : \mathcal{J} → \M^→\) be a category over \(\M^→\), with \(\mathcal{J}\) small. Then the free awfs on \(\mathcal{J}\) exists
|
||||
% and is algebraically-free on \(\mathcal{J}\).
|
||||
% \end{theorem}
|
||||
% Without going to much into the size issues, every locally presentable categoy satisfies \((\ast)\). And as \(\□\) is a presheaf
|
||||
% category over a countable category, it is locally presentable. Also by beeing a presheaf category makes it automatically cocomplete.
|
||||
% Without going to much into the size issues, every locally presentable category satisfies \((\ast)\). And as \(\□\) is a presheaf
|
||||
% category over a countable category, it is locally presentable. Also by being a presheaf category makes it automatically co-complete.
|
||||
%
|
||||
% We also won't clarify all the consequences that getting an awfs instead of a wfs, brings with it. For us the important
|
||||
% thing is, that every awfs has an underlying wfs. The free part of that statement unsures that this construction preserves
|
||||
|
@ -103,7 +103,7 @@ will be to restrict the fibrations to have the desired property.
|
|||
\subsubsection{Cofibrations and trivial fibrations}
|
||||
The short way of specifying this weak factorization system, is by saying
|
||||
the cofibrations are the monomorphisms. Another, longer way, but for the further development more
|
||||
enlightening is by formulating this as uniform lifting properties.
|
||||
enlightening is by formulating this as a uniform lifting properties.
|
||||
It is also not equivalent from the viewpoint of an awfs, as this definition has extra conditions on the
|
||||
chosen lifts.
|
||||
The condition to have uniform lifts, comes from \cite{CCHM} and generalized in \cite{gambinoFrobeniusConditionRight2017} . This requirement is motivated to have
|
||||
|
@ -112,33 +112,34 @@ explore this further.
|
|||
|
||||
\begin{definition}
|
||||
Let \(J : \mathcal{M} ↣ \A^→\) be subcategory which objects are a pullback stable class of morphisms in \A, and morphisms are
|
||||
the cartesian squares between them. The category \(J^⧄\) is called the category \emph{uniform right lifting morphisms} with respect
|
||||
the Cartesian squares between them. The category \(J^⧄\) is called the category \emph{uniform right lifting morphisms} with respect
|
||||
to \(\mathcal{M}\). Objects of \(J^⧄\) are said to have the \emph{uniform right lifting property}.
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}
|
||||
The category of \emph{uniform generating cofibrations} has as object monomorphisms into a cube \(C ↣ I^n\) of arbitraty dimension, and
|
||||
as morphism cartesian squares between those.
|
||||
The category of \emph{uniform generating cofibrations} has as object monomorphisms into a cube \(C ↣ \I^n\) of arbitrary dimension, and
|
||||
as morphism Cartesian squares between those.
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}
|
||||
A \emph{uniform trivial cofibration} is a right map with respect to the inclusion functor from the category of uniform generation cofibrations
|
||||
A \emph{uniform trivial fibration} is a right map with respect to the inclusion functor from the category of uniform generation cofibrations
|
||||
into \(\□^→\)
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
\todo{show that the cofib are all monos}
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
From this it is not immediately clear that the left maps are all monomorphisms, but it follows from
|
||||
\cite[Proposition 7.5]{gambinoFrobeniusConditionRight2017}.
|
||||
By Garners small object argument \cref{awfs:smallObject}, this gives rise to an awfs which we call \((\TCF,\FF)\) and an underlying wfs
|
||||
that we call \((\C_t,\F)\)
|
||||
\subsubsection{Trivial cofibrations and fibrations}
|
||||
|
||||
As we sketched above, the strategy will be to make more maps trivial cofibrations. This is done
|
||||
by making it harder to be a fibration. Before we give the definition in full generality, we
|
||||
need to adress which coequilizer we talk about percisely.
|
||||
need to address which coequalizer we talk about precisely.
|
||||
|
||||
Of course doing this only in the 2 dimensional case is not enough. For this we need to say what
|
||||
the “swap” maps are. What these should do is permutating the dimensions. So let \(Σ_k\) be the symmetric group
|
||||
the “swap” maps are. What these should do is permuting the dimensions. So let \(Σ_k\) be the symmetric group
|
||||
on \(k\) elements. For every \(σ' ∈ Σ_k\), we get a map from \( σ : \I^k → \I^k \), by \((π_{σ'(1)}, … , π_{σ'(k)})\),
|
||||
where \(π_l : \I^k → \I \) is the \(l\)-th projection. Also if we have a subcube \(f : \I^n \rightarrowtail \I^k\),
|
||||
where \(π_l : \I^k → \I \) is the \(l\)-th projection. Also if we have a sub-cube \(f : \I^n \rightarrowtail \I^k\),
|
||||
we get a pullback square of the following form
|
||||
\begin{equation*}
|
||||
\begin{tikzcd}
|
||||
|
@ -148,11 +149,11 @@ we get a pullback square of the following form
|
|||
\end{equation*}
|
||||
whose right arrow we call \(σf\).
|
||||
%
|
||||
Now we desrcibe our generating trivial cofibrations. We remeber example \cref{Leibniz:Ex:OpenBox}. We would
|
||||
Now we describe our generating trivial cofibrations. We remember example \cref{Leibniz:Ex:OpenBox}. We would
|
||||
like to do the same here, but a bit more general.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
Instead we are going for boxfillings in the context of a cube. The definition of those will be very similiar
|
||||
Instead we are going for box-fillings in the context of a cube. The definition of those will be very similar
|
||||
we will just work in the slice over a cube \(I^k\). We do the Pushout-product in the slice, and
|
||||
forget the slice to get a map in \(\□\).
|
||||
\begin{equation*}
|
||||
|
@ -162,14 +163,14 @@ forget the slice to get a map in \(\□\).
|
|||
\end{equation*}
|
||||
|
||||
What do we change by working in the slice?
|
||||
For intuiton let us first look at the case
|
||||
with a one dimensional context. The point in in this context ist the terminal object in \(\faktor{\□}{\I}\).
|
||||
For intuition let us first look at the case
|
||||
with a one dimensional context. The point in in this context is the terminal object in \(\faktor{\□}{\I}\).
|
||||
The interval in this cube category could be described as the pullback, of the interval in \(\□ = \faktor{\□}{\I^0}\)
|
||||
along the unique map \(\I → \I^0\), or in simpler words it is the left projection \(π_l : \I × \I → \I\).
|
||||
Let us now look what maps we have from the point into the interval \(\id_\I → π_l \). We get the two
|
||||
endpoint maps we expected, as \(⟨\id, 0⟩ \) and \(⟨\id, 1⟩\), but in this context we get an additional map,
|
||||
namely \(⟨\id, \id⟩\). If we would forget the context again (aka beeing in the slice), this is the diagonal of the square. From
|
||||
a type theoretic perspective this is realy not surprising. Here it amounts to the question, how many different terms
|
||||
namely \(⟨\id, \id⟩\). If we would forget the context again (aka being in the slice), this is the diagonal of the square. From
|
||||
a type theoretic perspective this is really not surprising. Here it amounts to the question, how many different terms
|
||||
of type \(\I\) can be produced. In an empty context the answer is two.
|
||||
\begin{align*}
|
||||
⊢ 0 : \I && ⊢ 1 : \I
|
||||
|
@ -189,8 +190,8 @@ this short note \cite{coquandVariationCubicalSets2014}, for a discussion see for
|
|||
The generalization of the boundary inclusion is straight forward. We just take any cube over \(\I^k\)
|
||||
\(ζ : \I^n → \I^k\) and a monomorphism \(c : C → \I^n\), this also induces an object in the slice by composition.
|
||||
Notice that we did not require that \( n ≥ k\).
|
||||
If we pack all of this into a definiton we get.
|
||||
\begin{definition}
|
||||
If we pack all of this into a definition we get.
|
||||
\begin{definition}\label{def:modelStructure:generatingTrivialCofibration}
|
||||
Let \(ζ : \I^n → \I^k\) be a cube over \(\I^k\) and \(c : C → \I^n\) monic. A map of the form
|
||||
\begin{equation*}
|
||||
\begin{tikzcd}
|
||||
|
@ -237,7 +238,7 @@ Again we will do this in a slice and forget the slice afterwards.
|
|||
\right)
|
||||
\end{equation*}
|
||||
Notice that we understand the vertical morphisms as objects of \(\□^→\) and the horizontal ones as morphism in \(\□^→\).
|
||||
Also notice, that the left diagramm is a square for which we use in our uniformity condition and the right one captures
|
||||
Also notice, that the left diagram is a square for which we use in our uniformity condition and the right one captures
|
||||
equivariance. And notice that the pushout-product of the columns yield trivial cofibrations. We will denote the resulting
|
||||
commutative square as
|
||||
\begin{equation}\label{devilSquare}
|
||||
|
@ -246,7 +247,7 @@ commutative square as
|
|||
\I^m × \I^l \arrow[r, "α×σ"] & \I^n × \I^l
|
||||
\end{tikzcd}
|
||||
\end{equation}
|
||||
Now we can finaly give the definition of uniform equivariant fibrations.
|
||||
Now we can finally give the definition of uniform equivariant fibrations.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}
|
||||
The category of \emph{generating uniform equivariant trivial cofibrations} has as object
|
||||
|
@ -263,19 +264,76 @@ Now we can finaly give the definition of uniform equivariant fibrations.
|
|||
\((\Ct,\F)\)
|
||||
\end{notation}
|
||||
|
||||
We will show that this is a modelstructure by using the theory of premodel structures
|
||||
\subsubsection{The Premodel Structure of Equivariant Cubical Sets}
|
||||
On our way to show that this is a model structure, we will use the theory of premodel structures
|
||||
\cites{bartonModel2CategoryEnriched2019}[section 3]{cavalloRelativeEleganceCartesian2022}[section 3]{solution}{sattlerCYLINDRICALMODELSTRUCTURES}.
|
||||
\todo{if there is time (there probably won't be) include the premodel theory and explain}
|
||||
This machinery gives us a nice condition to check if we are actually dealing with a modelstructure. But first we need to
|
||||
introduce the notion of a premodel structure.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}[{\cites{bartonModel2CategoryEnriched2019}[def. 3.1.1]{cavalloRelativeEleganceCartesian2022}}]\label{def:preModelStructure}
|
||||
A \emph{premodel Structure} on a finitely cocomplete and complete category \M consists of two weak factorization systems
|
||||
A \emph{premodel Structure} on a finitely co-complete and complete category \M consists of two weak factorization systems
|
||||
\((C,F_t)\) (the \emph{cofibrations} and \emph{trivial fibrations}) and \((C_t, F)\) (the \emph{trivial cofibrations} and \emph{fibrations})
|
||||
on \M such that \(C_t ⊆ C\) (or equivalently \(F_t ⊆ F\) ).
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
And also the definition of a property of such.
|
||||
\begin{remark}
|
||||
This structure ascend to all slices and is created by the corresponding forgetful functor. This should not be surprising, as model
|
||||
structures do the same.
|
||||
\end{remark}
|
||||
|
||||
As all trivial cofibrations are monomorphisms, we get immediately that the two defined factorization systems above form a
|
||||
premodel structure. Every premodel structure comes equipped with a notion of weak equivalences.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}[{\cite[Definition 3.1.3]{cavalloRelativeEleganceCartesian2022}}]
|
||||
We say that a morphism in a premodel structure is a weak equivalence if it factors
|
||||
as a trivial cofibration followed by a trivial fibration;
|
||||
we write \(W(C, F)\) for the class of such morphisms.
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
What is missing, is that these equivalences actually satisfy the 2-out-of-3 condition.
|
||||
The machinery of premodel structures gives us a nice condition to check if we are actually dealing with a model structure.
|
||||
But first we investigate a bit more structure our premodel structure possesses
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}[{\cite[Definition 3.2.1]{cavalloRelativeEleganceCartesian2022}}]
|
||||
A \emph{functorial cylinder} on a category \(E\) is a functor \(\I⊗(−) : E → E\) equipped with endpoint and contraction
|
||||
transformations fitting in a diagram as shown:
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}[column sep = large, row sep=large]
|
||||
\Id
|
||||
\arrow[r,"δ_0⊗(−)", dashed]
|
||||
\arrow[dr,"\id"']
|
||||
& \I ⊗ (−)
|
||||
\arrow[d,"ε⊗(−)" description, dashed]
|
||||
& \Id
|
||||
\arrow[l,"δ⊗(−)"',dashed]
|
||||
\arrow[dl,"\id"]
|
||||
\\
|
||||
{}
|
||||
& \Id
|
||||
&
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
An \emph{adjoint functorial cylinder} is a functorial cylinder such that \(I ⊗ (−)\) is a left adjoint.
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
\todo{mention \(ε\) in cubical set notation}
|
||||
We can see immediately that the functor \(\I × (−)\) the product with the interval is a functorial cylinder,
|
||||
and by \□ being a presheaf topos even an adjoint functorial cylinder. But for now it is not at all clear
|
||||
that this functor is relevant in a homotopical sense. This is captured by the next definition.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}[{\cite[Definition 3.2.5]{cavalloRelativeEleganceCartesian2022}}]
|
||||
A \emph{cylindrical} premodel structure on a category E consists of a premodel structure
|
||||
and adjoint functorial cylinder on E that are compatible in the following sense:
|
||||
\begin{itemize}
|
||||
\item \(∂ \⊗ (−)\) preserves cofibrations and trivial cofibrations;
|
||||
\item \(δ_k \⊗ (−)\) sends cofibrations to trivial cofibrations for \(k ∈ \{0, 1\}\).
|
||||
\end{itemize}
|
||||
\end{definition}\todo{clean up and explain}
|
||||
\todo{mention adhesiveness in Leibniz product chapter}
|
||||
|
||||
These properties are verified quickly, the map \(∂ : 1 + 1 → \I\) is monic and thus
|
||||
it follows from \cref{TODO}. We check the second property on generating cofibrations\todo{is this enough?},
|
||||
plugging in the definition of our functorial cylinder we see that this is by definition
|
||||
a trivial cofibration if set \(k = 0\) and \(m = 1\) in \cref{def:modelStructure:generatingTrivialCofibration}.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}[{\cite[Definition 3.3.3]{cavalloRelativeEleganceCartesian2022}}]
|
||||
We say a premodel category \M has the fibration extension property when for any fibration
|
||||
\(f : Y → X\) and trivial cofibration \(m : X → X′\), there exists a fibration \(f' : Y' → X'\) whose base change along \(m\) is
|
||||
|
@ -286,18 +344,6 @@ And also the definition of a property of such.
|
|||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}[{\cite[Definition 3.2.5]{cavalloRelativeEleganceCartesian2022}}]
|
||||
A \emph{cylindrical} premodel structure on a category E consists of a premodel structure
|
||||
and adjoint functorial cylinder on E that are compatible in the following sense:
|
||||
\begin{itemize}
|
||||
\item \(∂ \⊗ (−)\) preserves cofibrations and trivial cofibrations;
|
||||
\item \(δ_k \⊗ (−)\) sends cofibrations to trivial cofibrations for \(k ∈ \{0, 1\}\).
|
||||
\end{itemize}
|
||||
\end{definition}\todo{clean up and explain}
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
We get this characterizing theorem.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{theorem}[{\cite[Theorem 3.3.5]{cavalloRelativeEleganceCartesian2022}}]\label{thm:premodelIsModel} \todo{if this gets longer expanded give it its own section}
|
||||
Let \(\M\) be a cylindrical premodel category in which
|
||||
\begin{enumerate}
|
||||
|
@ -307,10 +353,56 @@ We get this characterizing theorem.
|
|||
Then the premodel structure on \(\M\) defines a model structure.
|
||||
\end{theorem}
|
||||
|
||||
The first item is fast verified, as all monomorhpisms are cofibrations.\todo{make a small lemma to prove it (closure properties got you covered)}
|
||||
The second condition we won't show directly. We will get for free if we construct fibrant universes, which we want to do anyway.
|
||||
The first item is fast verified, as all monomorphisms are cofibrations.\todo{make a small lemma to prove it (closure properties got you covered)}
|
||||
The second condition we won't show directly. We will get for free if we construct universes, which we want to do anyway.
|
||||
% Before we construct universes we will first talk about another property that follows from general
|
||||
% pre model structure theory. This property relates back to type theory, as it is the categorical side of
|
||||
% glue types. These keep track of type extension and are used to prove univalence. We will use it later to show
|
||||
% that the base of our constructed universe is fibrant.
|
||||
% In categorical terms it says the following.
|
||||
%
|
||||
% \begin{definition}[{\cite{sattlerEquivalenceExtensionProperty2017}}]
|
||||
% A cylindrical premodel structure has the equivalence extension
|
||||
% property when any weak equivalence \(e\) over an object \(A\) can be extended along any cofibration
|
||||
% \(i : A → B\) to a weak equivalence \(f\) over \(B\) with a specified codomain extending that of the original map:
|
||||
% \begin{eqcd*}
|
||||
% X_0
|
||||
% \arrow[rr,dotted]
|
||||
% \arrow[rd,"e"]
|
||||
% \arrow[rdd,"p_0"']
|
||||
% & & Y_0
|
||||
% \arrow[rd,dashed, "f"]
|
||||
% \arrow[rdd,dotted]
|
||||
% &
|
||||
% \\
|
||||
% {}
|
||||
% & X_1
|
||||
% \arrow[rr, crossing over]
|
||||
% \arrow[d,"p_1"]
|
||||
% \arrow[rrd,phantom,"\lrcorner" very near start]
|
||||
% & & Y_1
|
||||
% \arrow[d,"q_1"]
|
||||
% \\
|
||||
% {}
|
||||
% & A
|
||||
% \arrow[rr,"i"]
|
||||
% & & B
|
||||
% \end{eqcd*}
|
||||
% In a setting such as a presheaf topos where we have universe levels,
|
||||
% there is an additional requirement: for sufficiently large inaccessible cardinals
|
||||
% \(κ\), if \(p_0\), \(p_1\), and \(q_1\) are \(κ\)-small, so is the extended fibration.
|
||||
% \end{definition}
|
||||
%
|
||||
% We could have equivalently used \cite[Proposition 5.1]{sattlerEquivalenceExtensionProperty2017},
|
||||
% but this version aligns more direct with the data that we are given.
|
||||
% \begin{theorem}[{\cite[Theorem 3.3.3]{solution}}]
|
||||
% Let \(E\) be a locally Cartesian closed category with a cylindrical premodel
|
||||
% structure in which the cofibrations are the monomorphisms, and these are stable under
|
||||
% pushout-products in all slices. Then the equivalence extension property holds in \(E\).
|
||||
% \end{theorem}
|
||||
% The pushout product claim is verified by \cref{TODO}\todo{adhesive note in Leibniz chapter}
|
||||
|
||||
\subsubsection{Fibrant Universes}
|
||||
\subsubsection{Universes for Fibrations}
|
||||
In this section we will change notation between commutative diagrams and the internal language of our presheaf.
|
||||
As these tools can get quite technical and tedious to verify, we will only present the idea how these constructions
|
||||
work and refer for the technical details to the source material.
|
||||
|
@ -349,16 +441,16 @@ For example by the arguments in \cite[Section 7]{awodeyHofmannStreicherUniverses
|
|||
\arrow[u, "\Fib(f)"']
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
If the wfs, for that we try to classify the right maps, is functorial we might think of this as an internaliztaion
|
||||
of the \(\R\)-algbera structures on \(f\).
|
||||
If the wfs, for that we try to classify the right maps, is functorial we might think of this as an internalization
|
||||
of the \(\R\)-algebra structures on \(f\).
|
||||
|
||||
We will first construct classifying types, after that we construct universes from it.
|
||||
|
||||
In preperation of the fibrant case we will first classify the trivial fibrations.
|
||||
In preparation of the fibrant case we will first classify the trivial fibrations.
|
||||
We don't have any equivariance condition on them, and thus they are the same as in \cite[Section 2]{awodeyCartesianCubicalModel2023},
|
||||
when we assume \(Φ = Ω\).
|
||||
|
||||
Let us first think about the easiest case where the domain of auf trivial fibration is the terminal.
|
||||
Let us first think about the easiest case where the domain of the trivial fibration is the terminal.
|
||||
We should ask us what are the \TFF-algebra structures\todo{introduce notion above}. These are intuitively
|
||||
choice functions of uniform liftings against cofibrations. So let us think about them first. If we picture
|
||||
a lifting problem,
|
||||
|
@ -498,7 +590,7 @@ We now going to extract the classifying type for equivariant cubical fibrations.
|
|||
and cubical species. There exists the constant diagram functor \(Δ\) that sends a cubical set to the constant cubical species.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
Since \□ is complete this functor has a right adjoint\footnote{and also a left adjoint as \□ is cocomplete}
|
||||
Since \□ is complete this functor has a right adjoint\footnote{and also a left adjoint as \□ is co-complete}
|
||||
\(Γ\) compare \cite[Section 5.1]{solution}, which is given by
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{equation*}
|
||||
|
@ -589,7 +681,7 @@ and building the following pullback.
|
|||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
To see this is a fibration we will exhibit we exhibit a split of the classifying type of \(π_κ\).
|
||||
As the classifying type is pullback stable we get the following diagram
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}[row sep=large, column sep = large]
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}[]
|
||||
\dot{\mathcal{U}}_κ
|
||||
\pb
|
||||
\arrow[d,"π_κ"]
|
||||
|
@ -611,10 +703,10 @@ As the classifying type is pullback stable we get the following diagram
|
|||
The lower pullback square is a pullback of \(\Fib(p)\) along itself. This map has a split, namely the diagonal.
|
||||
To show that this classifies small fibrations, let us consider a small fibration \(f : A → X\).
|
||||
Because it is a small map we get it as a pull back along a cannonical map \(a : X → \mathcal{V}\).
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}[row sep=small, column sep=small]
|
||||
{}
|
||||
& {}
|
||||
& \dot{\mathcal{U}}
|
||||
& \dot{\mathcal{U_κ}}
|
||||
\arrow[dr]
|
||||
\arrow[dd]
|
||||
&
|
||||
|
@ -623,13 +715,13 @@ Because it is a small map we get it as a pull back along a cannonical map \(a :
|
|||
& |[alias=A]| A
|
||||
\arrow[rr,crossing over]
|
||||
\arrow[ru,dashed]
|
||||
& & \dot{\mathcal{V}}
|
||||
& & \dot{\mathcal{V}_κ}
|
||||
\arrow[dd]
|
||||
\\
|
||||
\Fib(A)
|
||||
\arrow[rr]
|
||||
\arrow[dr]
|
||||
& & \mathcal{U}
|
||||
& & \mathcal{U_κ}
|
||||
\arrow[dr]
|
||||
&
|
||||
\\
|
||||
|
@ -644,17 +736,229 @@ Because it is a small map we get it as a pull back along a cannonical map \(a :
|
|||
We get the lower square as a pullback as \Fib is pullback stable and \(\mathcal{U} = \Fib(\dot{\mathcal{V}})\).
|
||||
As \(f\) is a fibration, we get a split \(s\) of the fibration structure. And so we get a unique corresponding map
|
||||
\(s'\), which induces the required pullback square.
|
||||
|
||||
\end{proof}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}[{\cite[Definition 94]{awodeyCartesianCubicalModel2023}}]
|
||||
A map \(P → X\) is said to be a weak proposition if the projection \(P ×_X P → P\) is a trivial fibration.
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}
|
||||
P^2
|
||||
\arrow[r]
|
||||
\arrow[d]
|
||||
\pb
|
||||
& P
|
||||
\arrow[d]
|
||||
\\
|
||||
P
|
||||
\arrow[r]
|
||||
& X
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
Note that if either projection is a trivial fibration, then both are.
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{lemma}[{\cite[Lemma 95]{awodeyCartesianCubicalModel2023}}]\label{lem:modelStructure:weakProposition}
|
||||
For any \(A → X\), the classifying type \(\TFib(A) → X\) is a weak proposition. Moreover, the same is true for \(\Fib(A) → X\).
|
||||
\end{lemma}
|
||||
We again will give the proofidea, sort out the differences for the equivariant case and refer the reader to the
|
||||
source material for the technical details.
|
||||
\begin{proof}[Proofsketch:]
|
||||
We first prove the case for \(\TFib\) and afterwards reduce the case the \Fib case to it.
|
||||
We first note that if a map \(A → X\) is a trivial fibration, so is \(\TFib(A) → X\). This is
|
||||
because if we expand the definition and look at the \(+\)-algebra structure, the map \(η_x : X → X^+\)
|
||||
is always monic.
|
||||
|
||||
Now let \(f : A → X\) and consider the following diagram.
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}[column sep=tiny]
|
||||
\TFib(A) ×_X A
|
||||
\arrow[dd]
|
||||
\arrow[rr]
|
||||
& & |[alias=A]| A
|
||||
\\
|
||||
{}
|
||||
& \TFib(A) ×_X \TFib(A)
|
||||
\arrow[dl]
|
||||
\arrow[rr]
|
||||
& & \TFib(A)
|
||||
\arrow[dl]
|
||||
\\
|
||||
\TFib(A)
|
||||
\arrow[rr]
|
||||
& & |[alias=X]| X
|
||||
\arrow[from=A,to=X,crossing over, "f" near start]
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
Since \(\TFib\) is stable under pullback we hav that \( \TFib(\TFib(A) ×_X A) \) is isomporhic to
|
||||
\( \TFib(A) ×_X \TFib(A) \), and since the latter has a canonical section \(\TFib(A) ×_X A → \TFib(A) ×_X \TFib(A)\),
|
||||
the \(\TFib(A) ×_X A\) is a trivial fibration over \(\TFib(A)\). By our note above we see that also \( \TFib(A) ×_X \TFib(A)\) is
|
||||
a trivial fibration over \(\TFib(A)\).
|
||||
|
||||
For \Fib we trace now through the whole construction process, and reduce it to the case above. For the technical details
|
||||
we refer to the source material. For our deviation in the construction we need a few additional properties. Namely
|
||||
the constant diagram functor preserves monomorhpisms, which is obviously true, and that taking exponentials with the
|
||||
interval in cubical species preserves monomorhpisms. As \(Σ\) has only endomorphisms, this reduces again
|
||||
to a componentwise check in \□, where we already know it by \cref{TODO}.\todo{show this}
|
||||
\end{proof}
|
||||
\begin{remark}
|
||||
The source has an additional condition, that in our setting is true.
|
||||
\end{remark}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{lemma}[{\cite[Lemma 96]{awodeyCartesianCubicalModel2023}}]
|
||||
The univeres \(\mathcal{U}_κ\) satisfies \emph{realignment} in the following senes.
|
||||
Given a \(κ\)-small fibration \(g : A → X\) and a cofibration \(c : C → X\), let \(f_c : C → \mathcal{U}_κ\) classify the pullback
|
||||
\(c^∗A → C\). Then there is a classifying map \(f : X ↣ \mathcal{U}_κ\) for \(A\) with \(f c = f_c\).
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}[row sep = small, column sep = small]
|
||||
c^*F
|
||||
\arrow[rr]
|
||||
\arrow[dr]
|
||||
\arrow[dd]
|
||||
& & \dot{\mathcal{U}}_κ
|
||||
\arrow[dd]
|
||||
\\
|
||||
{}
|
||||
& |[alias=F]| A
|
||||
\arrow[ur,dashed]
|
||||
&
|
||||
\\
|
||||
C
|
||||
\arrow[rr, "f_c" near start]
|
||||
\arrow[rd,tail,"c"]
|
||||
& & \mathcal{U}_κ
|
||||
\\
|
||||
{}
|
||||
& |[alias=X]| X
|
||||
\arrow[ur,dashed,"f"]
|
||||
&
|
||||
\arrow[from=F, to=X, crossing over, "g" near start]
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
\end{lemma}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{proof}
|
||||
First, we extend this diagram by the small map classifier and, by realignment for HS-Universes \cref{TODO}\todo{make a lemma, or cite}
|
||||
we get an extension \(f_0\).
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}[row sep = small, column sep = small]
|
||||
c^*F
|
||||
\arrow[rr]
|
||||
\arrow[dr]
|
||||
\arrow[dd]
|
||||
& & \dot{\mathcal{U}}_κ
|
||||
\arrow[dd]
|
||||
\arrow[r]
|
||||
& \dot{\mathcal{V}}_κ
|
||||
\arrow[dd]
|
||||
\\
|
||||
{}
|
||||
& |[alias=F]| A
|
||||
\arrow[urr,dashed, crossing over]
|
||||
& &
|
||||
\\
|
||||
C
|
||||
\arrow[rr, "f_c" near start]
|
||||
\arrow[rd,tail,"c"]
|
||||
& & \mathcal{U}_κ
|
||||
\arrow[r]
|
||||
& \mathcal{V}_κ
|
||||
\\
|
||||
{}
|
||||
& |[alias=X]| X
|
||||
\arrow[urr,dashed,"f_0"]
|
||||
& &
|
||||
\arrow[from=F, to=X, crossing over, "g" near start]
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
Since \(g\) is a fibration we get a lift of \(f_1 : X → \U \) of \(f_0\) classifying the fibration structure.
|
||||
This gives us the following diagram in the base.
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}
|
||||
C
|
||||
\arrow[r,"f_c"']
|
||||
\arrow[rr,bend left, "\Fib(p)f_c"]
|
||||
\arrow[d, tail, "c"]
|
||||
& \U
|
||||
\arrow[r]
|
||||
& \V
|
||||
\arrow[d, equal]
|
||||
\\
|
||||
X
|
||||
\arrow[r,"f_1"]
|
||||
\arrow[rr, bend right, "Fib(p)f_1"']
|
||||
& \U
|
||||
\arrow[r]
|
||||
& \V
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
We can now pull back \(\Fib(p)\) along itself and rearrenge the data.
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}
|
||||
C
|
||||
\arrow[d,tail,"c"]
|
||||
\arrow[r,"{⟨f_1c,f_c⟩}"']
|
||||
\arrow[rr,bend left,"fc"]
|
||||
&[3em] \U ×_{\V} \U
|
||||
\arrow[r,"π_2"']
|
||||
\arrow[d,"π_1"]
|
||||
& \U
|
||||
\arrow[d]
|
||||
\\
|
||||
X
|
||||
\arrow[rr,bend right, "f_0"']
|
||||
\arrow[r,"f_1"]
|
||||
& \U
|
||||
\arrow[r]
|
||||
& \V
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
By \cref{lem:modelStructure:weakProposition} \(\Fib(\Vd) = \U → \V\) is a weak proposition, this means
|
||||
\(π_1\) is a trivial fibration and we get a lift \(f_2 : X → \U ×_{\V} \U\), by normal lifting properties.
|
||||
Taking \(f ≔ π_2 f_2\) gives another classifying map for the fibration structure, for which
|
||||
\(fc=f_c\) as required.
|
||||
\end{proof}
|
||||
|
||||
%This equips us with enough structure to show that the premodel structure above induces indeed a model structure, but
|
||||
%from a type theoretic perspective we are not satisfied yet. We want that \(\mathcal{U}\) itself is type, or in categorical
|
||||
%words a fibrant object. As we are focusing on the equivalence to spaces right now, this is out of scope of this document
|
||||
%and we refer the reader to \cite[Proposition 5.3.9]{solution}.
|
||||
\todo{show fibrancy, this is hard and long, but needed for the next part. Or admit defeat and write something here}
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
\todo{introduce Leibniz pullback exponential}
|
||||
\todo{introduced (unbiased) uniform fibrations and how they behave with leibniz constructions}
|
||||
\todo{hate my life}
|
||||
|
||||
\subsubsection{HS-Universe}
|
||||
Assume this as given for now, if we have time we can write this out \todo{delete it or write it out, and move it to some preliminary place}
|
||||
|
||||
\subsubsection{From Premodel Structure to Model Structure}
|
||||
From here on we assume our constructed universe is fibrant. \todo{hopefully we can get rid of this}
|
||||
We are now ready to verify the last precondition of \cref{thm:premodelIsModel}.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{proposition}
|
||||
Fibrant universes imply the fibrant extension property.
|
||||
\end{proposition}
|
||||
\begin{proof}
|
||||
Let \(f : A → X\) be a fibration and \(m : X → Y\) be a cofibration. Let \(κ\) be large enough so that
|
||||
\(f\) is \(κ\)-small. We can classify \(f\) by a map \(a : X → \U\) and get the following diagram in the base.
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}
|
||||
X \arrow[r,"a"] \arrow[d,"m"] & \U \arrow[d] \\
|
||||
X' \arrow[r] \arrow[ru, dashed,"a'"] & *
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
As \U is fibrant this gives us a lift \(a'\). We can then get the required fibration by pulling
|
||||
back \(π_κ\) along \(a'\).
|
||||
\begin{eqcd*}
|
||||
A
|
||||
\arrow[rr]
|
||||
\arrow[dr,dashed]
|
||||
\arrow[dd,"f"]
|
||||
& & \dot{\mathcal{U}}_κ
|
||||
\arrow[dd]
|
||||
\\
|
||||
{}
|
||||
& |[alias=F]| Y'
|
||||
\arrow[ur]
|
||||
&
|
||||
\\
|
||||
X
|
||||
\arrow[rr, "f_c" near start]
|
||||
\arrow[rd,tail,"c"]
|
||||
& & \mathcal{U}_κ
|
||||
\\
|
||||
{}
|
||||
& |[alias=X]| Y
|
||||
\arrow[ur,"a'"]
|
||||
&
|
||||
\arrow[from=F, to=X, crossing over, dashed]
|
||||
\end{eqcd*}
|
||||
Making the required diagram a pullback, by the double pullback lemma.
|
||||
\end{proof}
|
||||
|
||||
\subsection{Dedekind Cubes}
|
||||
We will also need a description of the model structure on the Dedekind cubes. It is similar in construction, we just
|
||||
|
@ -703,7 +1007,7 @@ of \(A\) that agrees with the partial element, where it is defined. So giving an
|
|||
\end{equation}
|
||||
%
|
||||
It is an opration that given \([φ]\) and \(f\) returns an \(a\) and a wittness that the upper triangle commutes.
|
||||
The lower one commuts automatically by the virtue of \(a\) beeing a term of type \(A\). Notice that uniformity
|
||||
The lower one commuts automatically by the virtue of \(a\) being a term of type \(A\). Notice that uniformity
|
||||
does not appear explicitly in this description, but happens automatically as pullback squares are the
|
||||
interpretation of substitutions, and the type thoeretic rules around substitution already imply a uniform
|
||||
choice of our lifts.
|
||||
|
|
1570
src/resource.bib
1570
src/resource.bib
File diff suppressed because it is too large
Load diff
Loading…
Reference in a new issue